Pointless Topology via Abstract Nonsense
In 1940. G.H. Hardy published his essay "A Mathematician's Apology" in which he used number theory as a prominent example for pure and inapplicable mathematics. He meant it seriously, not as a joke. To the defense of his apology (pun a bit intended), at the time only a handful of programmers thought about hash-tables, cryptosystems were yet to be widely implemented in E-commerce platforms, and not many people used FFT before 1965 (no one but Gauss, I think). Indeed, computers forced mathematicians to work harder and harder in order to keep annoying engineers away from their offices.
This post is about Stone Duality: a result that relates geometry and algebra using a mathematical framework known as "abstract nonsense", and gives rise to a perspective on topology which is self-admittedly pointless. This is undoubtedly an heroic attempt to achieve pureness and inapplicability. Alas, it turned out to be useful and practical as well. Many ideas about the design of programming languages owe it their existence.
Yet, I'm not going to discuss applications. My motivation here is missionary: everyone should know this stuff. It's not a matter of mathematical beauty (though it is mathematically beautiful), but a matter of usefulness. Conceptual usefulness, not practical. When I first studied it, I was really annoyed for not having studied it earlier, as it would have made so many things so much easier. In terms of "Aha!-moments per second", the experience of studying it ranks high on the list.
As abstract as this topic is (and I again refer the reader to the title), it's still among the most concrete and explicit settings in which many concepts, ideas and "mathematical slogans" can be demonstrated and motivated. The list is long, and it contains (for example) spectrum of rings, algebraic probability, topoi and "algebra is dual to geometry".
Before delving into the math, let's start with a soft overview using some heavy amount of hand-waving.
1. Overview
Generally, Stone duality relates geometric objects and algebraic objects. Specifically, it establishes a precise relation between the category $\mathrm{Top}$ of topological spaces with homeomorphisms between them and the category $\mathrm{Loc}$ whose objects are a certain type of lattices called "Locales".
Taking a geometric perspective, this duality is motivated by thinking of a "point" as an abstraction of the ability to zoom-in on an arbitrarily small area. So points are not taken as fundamental entities, but rather as an encapsulated limiting process: a "point" is identified with the collection of all of its neighbourhoods.
Now, since the set of all well-defined locations of a space can be characterized algebraically (more on this soon), we may potentially get 2 descriptions of the same thing: as a space of points with some notion of proximity, and as an algebraic structure of locations.
Alternatively, it's possible to start from an algebraic perspective by considering the Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra of the propositional logic of affirmative assertions. This requires some explaining.
The Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra of a logical theory $T$ is the quotient algebra obtained by factoring the algebra of its formulas by the congruence relation $p\sim q$ iff $p$ and $q$ are provably equivalent in $T$. For example, the Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra of classical propositional logic, is Boolean algebra.
A logical assertion is affirmative if it's finitarily confirmable whenever it's true (and refutative if it's finitarily disconfirmable whenever it's false). A good model of such assertions is provided by thinking of physical rulers. Given a ruler of length $N$, it may be possible to verify that an object is strictly shorter then $N$, but due to measurement error, it's impossible to verify that an object's length is exactly $N$. So the assertion "Zoidberg's height is less than 160cm" is affirmative, while the assertion "Zoidberg's height is at least 160cm" is not affirmative (it might be true if his height is exactly 160cm, but then it's not confirmable).
It's not hard to construct a logical theory for affirmative assertions, based on the observational content of logical connectives. For example, a finite conjunctions of affirmative assertions is an affirmative assertion, but an infinite conjunctions of affirmative assertions is not affirmative (when it's true, it requires an infinite number of tests to confirm). On the other hand, an infinite disjunctions of affirmative assertions is an affirmative assertion (whenever it's true, testing all those assertions sequentially until a true assertion is found, is guaranteed to terminate after a finite number of steps).
Such reasoning can be applied to the other connectives to form a logical theory called propositional geometric logic. Why "geometric"? This may be a good time to recall the etymology of the term "geometry" (keeping in mind the rulers from earlier): from Greek, combination of "ge" ("earth, land") and "metria" ("a measuring of"). "measurement of land".
This theory can be algebraically represented by the Lindenbaum–Tarski process described above (this is a gross simplification that ignores technical details - some of which I'll touch later). Again, this is a process of algebraizing geometry (literally!), which is apparently equivalent to the previous one.
Both perspectives - the geometric and the logical - have their merits, and they are priceless as a concretization of abstract thingies, whether within algebraic geometry (e.g. Zariski topology, topoi) or within computer science (e.g. domain theory).
2. Categorical Preliminaries
Let's briefly explore some concepts, central for what's coming.
First, I would like to suggest that despite its name, Stone duality is not necessarily about a duality. The way it relates geometry and algebra is important and interesting in general, even when the conditions are too weak for a proper duality. This weaker (yet rich) relation is adjunction. This is a categorical notion that relates two functors via a pair of natural transformations, which are themselves a way to relate two functors.
I won't explain categories and functors here: that's common knowledge, and the concepts are easy to understand simply by reading the definitions (which can be easily found). But I will say something about natural transformations and adjunctions, which might be somewhat less familiar and are certainly harder to grasp.
A natural transformation is a relation between two functors that share domain and codomain $F_1, F_2: C\rightarrow D$ (here $C$ and $D$ are categories). A natural transformation $T:F_1\rightarrow F_2$ assigns each object $X$ in $C$, a morphism $\eta_X$ in $D$, such that the so-called "naturality condition" holds: for any $(f:X\rightarrow Y)\in C$ the following diagram must commute: $$\require{AMScd} \begin{CD} F_1(X) @>F_1(f)>> F_1(Y)\\ @V\eta_XVV @VV\eta_YV\\ F_2(X) @>F_2(f)>> F_2(Y) \end{CD}$$
It's very instructive to think of a natural transformation as a homotopy) between the functors. So if $I$ denotes the interval category $0\rightarrow 1$, then a natural transformation $T:F_1\rightarrow F_2$ is a functor $I\times C\rightarrow D$ such that $T(0,X)=F_1(X)$ and $T(1,X)=F_2(X)$.
Another useful mental model comes from thinking about categories as graphs. The graph indexing category, denoted $\mathrm{GrIn}$, is the category $\mathrm{Ed} \underset{\text{tgt}}{\overset{\text{src}.}{\rightrightarrows}} \mathrm{Ve}$. Programmers would find it easy to think of this category as a defintion of a class for graphs. Its 2 objects ($\mathrm{Ed}$ and $\mathrm{Ve}$) represent the 2 types of entities constitute a graph (edges and vertices, respectively), and its 2 arrows represent the 2 relations that may hold in a graph: a vertex could be either a source of an edge or a target of an edge (or neither).
In this light, a functor $G:\mathrm{GrIn}\rightarrow\mathrm{Set}$ is a concrete graph ("an instance of the category"), and a natural transformation of two such functors is precisely the same thing as a graph homomorphism. This is an example of the categorical notion of a "diagram".
As for adjunctions, wikipedia says "adjunction is ubiquitous in mathematics". It also quotes Mac Lane: "adjoint functors arise everywhere". Be it as it may, I must admit I found it exceptionally tricky to grok when I first encountered it. But well, I ain't no mathematician.
So what's the big idea? The formal definitions are dry and unenlightening. The ingredients are two functors $\mathrm{A} \underset{G}{\overset{F}{\rightleftarrows}} \mathrm{B}$, two natural transformations, $\eta:1_A\rightarrow G\circ F$ (the unit) and $\epsilon:F\circ G\rightarrow 1_B$ (the counit), and conditions to relate them, namely "the triangle identities" $(\epsilon F)\circ(F\eta)=1_F$ and $(G\epsilon)\circ(\eta G)=1_G$. This definition blurs the asymmetry between $F$ and $G$, but it's fundamental: $F$ is left-adjoint to $G$ and $G$ is right- adjoint to $F$ (this is denoted $F\dashv G$).
The remedy for an unhelpful definition is a good example. Traditionally, adjunctions are introduced by an example of a free functor (as the left-adjoint) and a forgetful functor (as the right-adjoint). Such pairs are an absolutely common and important mathematical theme, but I find their pedagogical value doubtful. To their credit, they do make it easy to remember that generally left- adjoints "increase" and right-adjoints "decrease".
Instead, here are two examples that made it click for me.
The first example deals with numbers. Let $Z$ and $Q$ denote the integers and the rationals as categories whose morphisms are given by $\le$, and consider the inclusion $I:Z\rightarrow Q$ as a functor. Then floor $x\mapsto\lfloor x\rfloor$ is a functor $Q\rightarrow Z$ which is right-adjoint to $I$, and ceil $x\mapsto\lceil x\rceil$ is a functor $Q\rightarrow Z$ which is left-adjoint to $I$. I'll prove the left-adjointness for ceil, and leave floor as an exercise (that is to say, I'm lazy):
We have to provide 2 natural transformations, counit $\epsilon:C\circ I\rightarrow 1_Z$ and unit $\eta:1_Q\rightarrow I\circ C$ such that $1_C=\epsilon C\circ C\eta$ and $1_I=I\epsilon\circ\eta I$. The counit $\epsilon$ is trivial: $C\circ I:Z\rightarrow Z$ is $1_Z$ (it takes an integer, "casts it" as a rational number and ceils it, and it's trivially monotone).
As for the unit $\eta$, the functor $I\circ C:Q\rightarrow Q$ ceils a rational number, and "casts it" back to $Q$, and it maps $x\le y$ to $\lceil x\rceil\le\lceil y\rceil$ in $Q$. This is a natural transformation, since for all $x\le y$ the following naturality diagram commutes: $$\require{AMScd} \begin{CD} 1_Q(x) @>I_Q(x\le y)=(x\le y)>> 1_Q(y)\\ @V\eta(x)=(x \le\lceil x\rceil) VV @VV\eta(y)=(y \le\lceil y\rceil)V\\ I\circ C(x)=\lceil x\rceil @>I\circ C(x\le y)=(\lceil x\rceil\le \lceil y\rceil)>> I\circ C(x)=\lceil y\rceil \end{CD}$$
Essentially, the natural morphism of $\eta$ is $x\Rightarrow x\le\lceil x\rceil$, and it's easy to check that the triangle identities hold ($1_C=\epsilon C\circ C\eta\Leftrightarrow (x\le x)(C(x\le\lceil x\rceil))=x\le\lceil x\rceil$ etc).
The second example also deals with order. This is not a coincidence. As a matter of fact, order theory is by many means a simplified version of category theory (a perspective that has its own name, "decategorification"). And since order theory is central to Stone duality, let's take this opportunity to recall some definitions.
A preorder is a reflexive and transitive relation, a proset is a set equipped with a preorder, a partial order is an antisymmetric preorder, and a poset is a set equipped with a partial order. The process that takes prosets to posets (via the equivalence $x\equiv y$ iff $x\le y$ and $y\le x$) is functorial, and left-adjoint to the forgetful-functor $\mathrm{Poset}\rightarrow\mathrm{Preorder}$. If $X$ is a set with some order, then the set with the opposite order is denoted $X^\text{op}$.
The meet of two elements $x,y$, denoted $x\land y$, is their greatest lower bound, or infimum (it might not exist), and the join of two elements, denoted $x\lor y$, is their least upper bound, or supremum (it might also not exist). Obviously, join and meet are dual (meaning, $z=x\land y$ in $X$ if and only if $z=z\lor y$ in $X^\text{op}$). In fact, they are the decategorification of the categorical notions of limit and colimit.
A poset in which any two elements have both a unique meet and a unique join is called a lattice. When all arbitrary sets are bounded, the lattice is said to be complete. An easy fact with deep consequences, is that lattices are algebraic structures. So if we're given a poset with infimums and supremum, we may replace the partial-order with 2 binary operations, and lose no information ($x=\land{x,y}\Leftrightarrow x\le y\Leftrightarrow y=\lor{x,y}$). The deepness is due to the analogy between lattices and Cartesian-closed categories, and it has much to do with Stone duality.
We're ready for the example: Let $X$ be a lattice, and let $\delta:X\rightarrow X\times X$ be the diagonal mapping $x\mapsto(x,x)$. Then it has a (unique) right-adjoint, the meet operation $\land:X\times X\rightarrow X$ and a (unique) left-adjoint, the join operation $\lor:X\times X\rightarrow X$. Essentially, the meet operation is a right-adjoint because $(a,a)\le(x,y)\Leftrightarrow a\le x\land y$, and the join operation is a loft-adjoint because $x\lor y\le z\Leftrightarrow(x,y)\le(z,z)$.
To conclude, I'll just mention that the composition of two adjoint functors give rise to a monad, and that any monad is representable as an adjunction. It should be noted that while the discussion above focused on adjoint functors, adjunction is a concept that applies generally in 2-categories. The idea is the same: a prototypical 2-category is the category $\mathrm{Cat}$ of small categories as objects, functors as morphisms and natural-transformation as 2-cells.
This should feel familiar to programmers. After all, a monad is just a monoid in the category of endofunctors. No problem.
3. Heyting Algebras
The central objects of Stone duality are Heyting algebras. Those are the "intermediate objects" used to relate topologies and locales. Such structures come up naturally in 2 different contexts, and induce a nontrivial connection between them:
- As the structure of the Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra of some logical theories.
- As the structure of the open-sets of all topological spaces.
Explicitly, an Heyting algebra is a distributive lattice with implications. A lattice is distributive whenever meets distribute over joins ($x\land(y\lor z)=(x\land y)\lor(x\land z)$, like unions distribute over intersections), and implications are defined via the equational relation $z\le x\rightarrow y \Leftrightarrow z\land x\le y$. As a programmer at heart, I intuitively think of Heyting algebras as "exponentiated lattices" and of implications as analogous to Currying: $\mathrm{hom}(Z,Y^X)\cong\mathrm{hom}(Z\times X, Y)$.
In the logical context, the underlying order reflects entailments and implications are, well, implications. The algebraization of propositional intuitionistic logic is a Heyting algebra, and the algebraization of propositional geometric logic is a complete Heyting algebra (shortly, cHa). While the first result is easy, the second is not. The difference is due to finitary presentations. This is a rather technical subject, so I will only review it briefly.
An algebraic theory $T$ consists of some operations (of arbitrary arities) and some laws (which are equations $e_1=e_2$ where the $e_i$s are compositions of the operations). A $T$-algebra is an instantiation of $T$ in terms of a carrier set and functions. There are many instantiations of a theory (e.g. there are many groups in group theory), so how could one single out a specific instantiation of interest?
The algebraic approach is to use presentations. A presentation $T\langle G|R \rangle$ is a set of generators $G$ and a set of equational relations $R$. There could be many $T$-algebras that model a given presentation, so we still haven't singled out a specific instantiation. But we could try looking for the most "restrictive" model in the sense that it factors through any other model, and call it the model of the presentation. When such a universal construction exists, we say that this $T$-algebra is presented by the presentation $T\langle G|R \rangle$.
Often, this is well and sound. For example, if $T$ is a finitary algebraic theory, then any presentation $T\langle G|R \rangle$ presents a $T$-algebra - and this is the case for propositional intuitionistic logic. But propositional geometric logic is not finitary. Fortunately, it still presents (and its presentations are complete Heyting algebras), but proving this takes some effort.
In a sharp change of direction, a topology $\Omega X$ is also a complete Heyting algebra. This is not obvious: It is surely a lattice (w.r.t. unions and intersections as joins and meets). And by definition, arbitrary joins of open sets are open. But arbitrary meets of open sets are not necessarily open - so how come is it complete? And where are the implications?
Time for a methodological detour. There are 3 different categories whose objects are complete Heyting algebras:
- $\mathrm{cHa}$: In which morphisms preserve both arbitrary joins and arbitrary meets.
- $\mathrm{Frm}$ (Frames): In which morphisms preserve arbitrary joins, but only finite meets.
- $\mathrm{Loc}$ (Locales): In which morphisms preserve arbitrary meets, but only finite joins.
This is certainly non-obvious, and implies: (A) As a structure, being either a Frame or a Locale is equivalent to being a cHa. (B) A morphism may preserve arbitrary joins, but not arbitrary meets (and vice versa). I won't prove it here, but just hint that given a frame, we can define implications by $a\rightarrow b := \lor{c:c\land a\le b}$, and that actually stronger statements hold (e.g. a lattice is a frame if and only if it is cHa). Also, note that the categories $\mathrm{Frm}$ and $\mathrm{Loc}$ are dual.
Back to topology. We showed above that open-sets have the structure of a frame, and now we know that any frame is a cHa. So topologies are indeed structured as complete Heyting algebras. But this is hardly satisfactory. How, concretely, should we understand infinitary meets of open sets?
Let $V_i$ be an infinite sequence of open sets. Then in general $\land V_i$ won't be given as an intersection of open sets. What then? It should satisfy $\land V_i\le V_j$, and if $W\le V_i$ for all $i$ then $W\le\land V_i$. So $\land V_i$ should be the "largest" open set contained in $\cap V_i$, that is, $\land V_i=\mathrm{int}{(\cap V_i)}$. Implications then, are given by $U\rightarrow V := \mathrm{int}(U^c\cup V)$.
4. Localification and Spatialization
Alright, now we're in business. We are about to construct a localification functor $\mathrm{Lc}:\mathrm{Top}\rightarrow\mathrm{Loc}$ that abstracts away the points of topological spaces and a specialization functor $\mathrm{Sp}:\mathrm{Loc}\rightarrow\mathrm{Top}$ that maps locales to the "simplest" topological space they describe. Then we'll show those two functors are adjoint: $\mathrm{Lc}\dashv\mathrm{Sp}$.
From the discussion above it is clear that we have a contravariant functor from $\mathrm{Top}$ to $\mathrm{Frm}$: it sends a continuous function $f:X\rightarrow Y$ (which is a morphism in $\mathrm{Top}$) to a morphism $f^{-1}:\Omega Y\rightarrow\Omega X$ in $\mathrm{Frm}$. This is just the definition of continuity.
Equivalently, we have a covariate functor $\mathrm{Lc}:\mathrm{Top}\rightarrow\mathrm{Loc}$. This calls for some clarification: this functor maps $f:X\rightarrow Y$ to the opposite arrow of $f^{-1}:\Omega Y\rightarrow\Omega X$, which is a morphism $\Omega X\rightarrow\Omega Y$ in $\mathrm{Loc}$, but this is a formal construction that seems to say nothing about this arrow as a map. Yet, it does: this arrow should preserve arbitrary meets and finite joins, and generally those arrows should respect (opposite) compositions w.r.t to this contravariant functor.
Localification of a topological space is an abstraction, and it leads to information loss: many different topological spaces may induce the same locale (easy example: any set equipped with the trivial topology ${X,\emptyset}$ induces the same locale. So it's impossible in general to restore the original points of the space from a locale).
However, given a locale we can still obtain a spatial object (i.e. a space with points) which is categorically optimal. This requires a recipe to (optimally) represent points of a locale $L$ (which is a "pointless space") together with a topological structure that is consistent with the locale. The topological space $\mathrm{Sp}(L)$ is called "the spectrum of $L$". The topology of the spectrum is a locale $\mathrm{Lc}(\mathrm{Sp}(L))$ which is homomorphic to $L$ (i.e. there is a locale-morphism $L\rightarrow\mathrm{Lc}(\mathrm{Sp}(L))$).
Actually, instead of a recipes - how about 4? The following are 4 suitable approaches - each has its own ups and downs. All of those constructions "work" in a categorical sense: locale-morphisms preserve points.
Recipe 1: Points as Frame Morphisms
Given a space $(X,\Omega X)$, there is a natural one-one correspondence between points $x_0\in X$ and functions $f_{x_0}:{0}\rightarrow X$ given by $0\mapsto x_0$. The set ${0}$ has a unique topology (the trivial one, ${{0},\emptyset}$), thus we have a canonical $\mathrm{Frm}$-morphism $f_{x_0}^{-1}:\Omega X\rightarrow\Omega{0}$.
The construction is easily interpretable: Since the elements of $L$ are meant to model "locations", then a point can be naturally thought of in terms of all the locations containing it. So a point can be identified with a characteristic function $\mu:L\mapsto{0,1}$ that preserve arbitrary meets and finite joins (finite, since an arbitrary join of non-neighborhoods may be a neighborhood), i.e., $\mu$ is a $\mathrm{Loc}$-morphism. Its dual is exactly the $\mathrm{Frm}$-morphism constructed above.
To specify $\mathrm{Sp}:\mathrm{Loc}\rightarrow\mathrm{Top}$, we need to functorially map $L$ to open sets defined over those points. The object part is constructed by associating each $\ell\in L$ with an open set $\phi(\ell):={\mu\in\mathrm{Sp}(L) | \mu(\ell)=1}$ (it's not hard to show that this is indeed a topology - and it should be intuitively clear by the above interpretation regarding points).
As for the morphism-part, we need to describe how to functorially associate a $\mathrm{Loc}$-morphism $\mu:L\rightarrow M$ with a continuous function $f_\mu:\mathrm{Sp}(L)\rightarrow\mathrm{Sp}(M)$. Since we model points in $\mathrm{Sp}(L)$ and $\mathrm{Sp}(M)$ as $\mathrm{Frm}$-morphisms, $f_\mu$ will map points by composing them with the $\mathrm{Frm}$-morphism $\mu^\mathrm{op}:M\rightarrow L$, so $f_\mu(x):=x\circ\mu^\mathrm{op}$. This definition "compiles": any $x\in\mathrm{Sp}(L)$ is a $\mathrm{Frm}$-morphism $L\rightarrow{0,1}$, so $x\circ\mu^\mathrm{op}$ is a $\mathrm{Frm}$-morphism $M\rightarrow{0,1}$, which means $f_\mu(x)=x\circ\mu^\mathrm{op}\in\mathrm{Sp}(M)$.
Recipe 2: Points as Completely Prime Filters
The second construction is also easily interpretable. First, recall the definitions:
- A filter $\mathscr{F}$ on a lattice $L$ is a non-empty subset of $L$ such that $\mathscr{F}=\uparrow G$ for some $G\subseteq L$ and $x,y\in\mathscr{F}\Rightarrow x\land y\in\mathscr{F}$.
- A filter $\mathscr{F}$ on a lattice $L$ is Prime iff $a_1\lor a_2\in\mathscr{F}$ implies that $a_1\in\mathscr{F}$ or $a_2\in\mathscr{F}$.
- A filter $\mathscr{F}$ on a lattice $L$ is Completely Prime iff the above holds for arbitrary joins: $\bigvee{a_i\in\mathscr{F}}\Rightarrow\exists a_i$ s.t. $a_i\in\mathscr{F}$.
Thinking again of a "point" as a collection of locations, filters become an obvious candidates to model points. The restriction to completely-prime filters meant to mitigate the issue (mentioned above) regarding arbitrary-joins and can be understood as allowing only neighbourhood systems as admissible filters (indeed, in topological spaces any collection $\mathscr{U}_x:={U\in\Omega X | x\in U}$ is a completely-prime filter).
This construction is equivalent to the first one: Any completely-prime filter $\mathscr{F}\subset L$ can be associated with the locale-morphism $\mu:L\rightarrow {0,1}$ s.t. $\mu(x)=1\Leftrightarrow x\in F$, and any locale- morphism $\mu:L\rightarrow {0,1}$ induced the completely-prime filter $\mathscr{F}:={x\in L | \mu(x)=1}$.
The object part of $\mathrm{Sp}:\mathrm{Loc}\rightarrow\mathrm{Top}$ is constructed by associating each $\ell\in L$ with an open set $\Sigma_\ell:={\mathscr{F}\subset L | \ell\in\mathscr{F}}$ where $\mathscr{F}$ is completely prime. This is a topology, since $\Sigma_0=\emptyset$, $\Sigma_1={\mathscr{F} | \mathscr{F}\subset L}$ (completely prime filters), $\Sigma_{a\land b}=\Sigma_a\cap\Sigma_b$ and $\Sigma_{\bigvee{a_i}}=\bigcup\Sigma_{a_i}$.
The morphism-part is constructed as following: let $\psi:L\rightarrow M$ be a locale-morphism, and define $\mathrm{Sp}(\psi):\mathrm{Sp}(L)\rightarrow\mathrm{Sp}(M)$ by $\mathscr{F}\mapsto(\psi^*)^{-1}(\mathscr{F})$ where $\psi^*$ is the left Galois adjoint of $\psi$ (and since $\psi^*$ is a $\mathrm{Frm}$-morphism and $\mathscr{F}$ is completely prime over $L$, then $(\psi^*)^{-1}(\mathscr{F})$ is completely prime over $M$ - so $\mathrm{Sp}(\psi)$ maps points to points). The map $\mathrm{Sp}(\psi)$ is continuous, since $(\mathrm{Sp}(\psi))^{-1}(\Sigma_a)=\Sigma_{\psi^*(a)}$, thus - $$(\mathrm{Sp}(\psi))^{-1}(\Sigma_a)={\mathscr{F} | \mathrm{Sp}(\psi)(\mathscr{F})=(\psi^*)^{-1}(\mathscr{F})\in\Sigma_a}={\mathscr{F}|a\in(\psi^*)^{-1}(\mathscr{F})}={\mathscr{F}|\psi^*(a)\in\mathscr{F}}=\Sigma_{\psi^*(a)}$$
Recipe 3: Points as Principal Prime Ideals
The third construction models points as principal prime ideals. It is equivalent to the second one, since principal prime ideals are dual to completely prime filters (heuristically, a principal prime ideal is a minimal collection of "negligible sets" that contains a point).
Recipe 4: Points as Meet-Irreducible Elements
The forth construction essentially follows from the third: an element $\ell\in L$ is meet-irreducible whenever the principle ideal $\downarrow\ell$ is also prime. Alternatively, it follows from the second construction: if $\mathscr{F}$ is a completely-prime filter, then $\ell_\mathscr{F}:=\{\bigvee{x\in L | x \not\in \mathscr{F}}\}$ is meet-irreducible, and if $\ell\in L$ is meet- irreducible, then $\mathscr{F}_\ell:=\{x\in L | x\not\le\ell\}$ is a completely- prime filter. Moreover, $\ell_{\mathscr{F}_\ell}=\ell$ and $x\in\mathscr{F}_{\ell_\mathscr{F}}\Leftrightarrow x\in\mathscr{F}$.
Now the functor $\mathrm{Sp}:\mathrm{Loc}\rightarrow\mathrm{Top}$ is very simple (but less "interpretable"). The object part is given by $\ell\in L\mapsto\{p\in L | \ell\not\le p\}$ (so $L$ is mapped into a topology), and the morphism part is $(\psi:L\rightarrow M)\mapsto({p\in L | \ell\not\le p}\mapsto {\psi(p) | p\in L, \ell\not\le p})$ which is continuous.
The Adjunction
First, as promised, let's see that locale-morphisms preserve points. It seems easiest to show that any locale-morphism $\mu:L\rightarrow M$ sends meet- irreducible elements to meet-irreducible elements: So let $\ell\in L$ be meet- irreducible, and assume that for $x,y\in M$ we have $x\land y\le\mu(\ell)$.
Since $L$ is a complete lattice and $\mu$ preserves arbitrary meets, it is the upper-component in a unique Galois connection $(\mu^*, \mu)$ (that is, $\mu^*:M\rightarrow L$ and $\mu^*(a)\le b\Leftrightarrow a\le\mu(b)$). Thus $x\land y\le\mu(\ell)$ implies $\mu^*(x)\land\mu^*(y)=\mu^*(x\land y)\le\ell$, and since $\ell$ is meet-irreducible in $L$ then assuming w.l.g $\mu^*(x)\le\ell$ implies $x\le\mu(\ell)$ and $\mu(\ell)$ is meet-irreducible in $M$.
Finally - the functors $\mathrm{Lc}:\mathrm{Top}\rightarrow\mathrm{Loc}$ and $\mathrm{Sp}:\mathrm{Loc}\rightarrow\mathrm{Top}$ are adjoint, $\mathrm{Lc}$ to the left and $\mathrm{Sp}$ to the right, with unit $\lambda:\mathrm{Id}_\mathrm{Top}\rightarrow\mathrm{Sp}\circ\mathrm{Lc}$ and counit $\sigma:\mathrm{Lc}\circ\mathrm{Sp}\rightarrow\mathrm{Id}_\mathrm{Loc}$.
The natural transformation corresponds to the counit $\sigma$ is: $$\require{AMScd} \begin{CD} (\mathrm{Lc}\circ\mathrm{Sp})(L) @>f_{|\{\mathscr{F}\}}>> (\mathrm{Lc}\circ\mathrm{Sp})(M)\\ @V\sigma_L:=(\phi_L)_*VV @VV\sigma_M:=(\phi_M)_*V\\ L @>f>> M \end{CD}$$
Where $L,M$ are locales, $f:L\rightarrow M$ is a locale-morphism, $f_{|{\mathscr{F}}}$ is $f$ considered as a set-function restricted to completely prime filters over $L$, and $\phi_L:L\rightarrow(\mathrm{Lc}\circ\mathrm{Sp})(L)$ is a $\mathrm{Frm}$-morphism defined as $\ell\mapsto\Sigma_\ell$ (so $\sigma_L:=(\phi_L)_*$ is its right Galois adjoint, hence a $\mathrm{Loc}$-morphism).
Recall that $(f^*)^{-1}:\mathrm{Sp}(L)\rightarrow\mathrm{Sp}(M)$, where $f^*$ is the left Galois adjoint to $f$, maps continuously completely prime filters over $L$ to completely prime filters over $M$, so $((f^*)^{-1})^{-1}=f^*$ maps open- sets from $\Omega\mathrm{Sp}(M)$ to open sets from $\Omega\mathrm{Sp}(L)$, which makes a $\mathrm{Frm}$-morphism, thus $f_{|{\mathscr{F}}}$ is a $\mathrm{Loc}$-morphism.
The natural transformation corresponds to the unit $\lambda$ can be constructed similarly.
5. Spatiality and Sobriety
So far, we have constructed an adjunction - which is truly great. But we were promised a duality!
A duality is expected when the topology is rich enough to render points useless. So obviously, the axiom $T_0$ is a precondition for the possibility of reconstructing points from locations. But it's not enough: different $T_0$ spaces may still have the same locales.
One way to proceed, is by looking for a stronger separation axiom (but as weak as possible), that allows restoring the points of a space from its topology. Turns out, this separation axiom is $T_D$: for each $x\in X$ there is an open $x\in U$ such that $U/{x}$ is open as well (note: $T_1\Rightarrow T_D\Rightarrow T_0$).
Indeed, for $T_D$ spaces, we have the following theorem (Thron): Let $X$ be a $T_D$-space, let $Y$ be a $T_0$-space and let $\Phi:\Omega(Y)\cong\Omega(X)$ be a lattice isomorphism. Then there is precisely one continuous mapping $f:X\rightarrow Y$ such that $\Phi = \Omega(f)$. Consequently, if both $X$ and $Y$ are $T_D$ then the $f$ is a homeomorphism.
But apparently, $T_D$ spaces are not very useful (such are the rumors, anyway). A better characterization is that of sobriety: a space $X$ is said to be sober if there are no meet-irreducible open sets other than $X$ ("No neighbourhood systems without a point"). It's also true that a space $X$ is sober if and only if the filters $U(x)$ are precisely the completely prime ones.
The constructions above should have made clear that "sobriety works": let $Y$ be sober and let $X$ be arbitrary. Then the continuous maps $f:X\rightarrow Y$ are in a one-one correspondence with the $\mathrm{Frm}$-morphisms $h:\Omega(Y)\rightarrow\Omega(X)$ (given by $f\mapsto f^{-1}$).
Sobriety is not a separation axioms, but rather, it is a type of "completeness": zooming-in always leads to a point. There are no "missing point" in Sober spaces. $T_D$ does not imply Sobriety, and Sobriety does not imply $T_D$. But any Hausdorff space is sober, any finite $T_0$-space is sober, any Noetherian Alexandroff Space is sober, and (my sources tell me) posets with the Scott topology are typically sober. So sobriety is common.
A locale $L$ is spatial only when it is isomorphic to the topology of its own spectrum. Otherwise, it is not isomorphic to the topology of any space. So $L$ is spatial iff $\sigma_L:\mathrm{Lc}(\mathrm{Sp}(L))\rightarrow L$ is a complete lattice isomorphism. $\mathrm{Sp}(L)$ is always sober.
Historically, Stone duality was first proved for the special case of locales which are Boolean algebras. Stone was motivated by his work on functional analysis: he was interested in a spectral representation theory for operators on Hilbert spaces, and noted that abstractly, Boolean algebras are equivalent to Boolean rings, which are "spaces of projections" (all their elements are idempotent).
Stone showed that any Boolean algebra is spatial, and its spectrum is a topological space which is rather exotic: it is compact, totally disconnected and Hausdorff (such spaces are now called "Stone spaces"). The importance of this theorem resides in the fact that it leads to a representation theorem for Boolean algebras: any abstract Boolean algebra is isomorphic to a concrete Boolean algebra (i.e. a field of sets).